2024#

April#

Being” is said in many ways.

Metaphysics, Aristotle

It is first of all said, and “to be said” requires what is said to be expressible in language. Every linguistic form is a representation. Therefore, something said is necessarily representative of some other thing. What a representation is and what it is representative of is left vague in the beginning, but the form of representation is not: language.

In order to understand the initial statement, one then turns to an analysis of language in order to clarify what could possibly be meant by a thing which can be said. A description of language is a necesary component of any exposition that wants to analyze the ways in which “being” is said. In making this description, one immediately encounters the essential problem in ontological endeavors: describing the operation of “description”” is itself a description.

Every system of thought, by objectifying the world, makes an object of itself within that system. “System” in this sense is synonymous with and equivalent to “language”.

For instance, lingustic representations possess the property of standing for things they themselves are not.

Note

Let “R” stand for things that are red.

Let “B” stand for things that are blue.

Here a letter, “R” or “B” , stands in place of something else. These letters are representations. Note the letter “R”” is not a thing that is red, except in circumstances where it is printed in red ink. Rather, it symbolizes the conjunction in thought of elements that possess the attribute of “being red”. The letter “R” makes an abstraction of the elements we agree belong to it.

On the other hand, there are sometimes classes of words that stand for themselves, or at least include themselves in that for which they stand. For example, the word “word” is a word that stands for the thing which it is,

Word” is a word.

However, a crucial distinction must be drawn in these cases. The quotation marks in the preceding example are not frivolities. They are a necessary component of the proposition, for they provide a boundary that outlines a thing’s name. Sans quotation marks, the proposition descends into senselessness,

Word is a word.

This analysis hinges on the realization first proffered by Tarski that there is a consequential difference between the language in which we speak propositions of a language and the language in which we speak about the propositions of a language.

The language one speaks is not necessarily the language about which one speaks.

Confusion often results when the same language performs both functions. In the case of mathematics, where the proposition language is that of, say, arithmetic, and the description language that of logic, the distinction is easier to maintain. When doing philosophy, the different levels of speech often waver and blur together, leading to confusion. For the purposes of clarity, quotation marks serve the function of referring to the name of the concept addressed whereas a unquoted word expresses what is meant by the concept. This lack of clarity throughout history is one of the root causes of Martin Heidegger’s deconstruction of “being” in the early twentieth century.

If the goal is to define “being”, then one can only succeed at the level of description. A description about a “ being “ is incapable of saying what is meant by “being”.

May#

When one authentically speaks the phrase “I know this”, one understands this to be meant in the context of certainy. “Knowledge”, if the term is to mean anything at all, must be defined in terms of certainty. “It is known” must be replaceable in all instances with “it is certain

The question of what is certain has no obvious or immediate answer, and so the existence of pure knowledge, of a kind that is absolute and without condition, is called into question. The world and all of its contents seem so hopelessly dependent on the subjective experience that one cannot truly convince one’s self that it exists in the absence of the subject.

The world presents itself, but the basis for the knowledge of this presentation is its representation to the self.

Everything imaginable is contained in, or possibly equal to, the enumeration of all possible representations. What cannot be imagined is precisely that which cannot be represented to the self. If a possibility exists that cannot be imagined, then it is only because “self” does not entail the totality of possibility. This can only occur if the representations presented to the self are incomplete, that is, if the presentation lacks content that cannot be comprehended through its representative form.

If you do know that “here is one hand”, we’ll grant you all the rest.

On Certainty, Wittgenstein

If the objective is to produce a certain fact, then all assumptions must be removed and one must start from nothing. Only the production of a fact from nullity would be able to satisfy any reasonable definition of “certainty”. If a fact derives from a prior assumption, then the fact is only as certain as its constitutive assumptions. Therefore, the question of the validity of the concept of “certainy” reduces to the question of whether positive knowledge can be derived from nothing.

It is a maxim of post-Kantian philosophy that what is known must be known through the experience of “knowing”, and thus it must be conditioned by experience. Knowledge of a thing is knowledge of the sensuous experience of the thing and what the sensuous cannot present to experience cannot be known.

For any object of experience, its attributes may be abstracted away in thought, but even an indeterminate object must possess a condition of determination for being able to be an object of experience; it is this form of determination that Kant identifies as “ a priori “. If, from a thing, its manifest qualities are subtracted, one is left with the pure abstract relation that sensuous experience deploys in order to perform the ontological operation of objectification.

The operands of the objectification are the experience for which the object is the object thus identified by experience. This operation yields a unique index, which one is inclined to call an object’s “name”. In other words, receptivity to naming is a prerequisite for being knowable. A thing cannot be known unless it can be named.

The inverse does not follow. One cannot conclude from “if a thing cannot be named, then it cannot be known” that “if a thing cannot be known, then a thing cannot be named”. If the latter were the case, then one would lack a proper name for “ nothing “.

June#

What is not truly one being is not truly one being either.

Leibniz Letters, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz

To say the same thing in a different way,

To be a being is to be a being.

Apparently tautological in form, the exact meaning of the Liebniz’s proposition can only be understood through the emphasis placed on its constituent words, which in turn immediately enriches its otherwise vacuous content. In this way, the words in Leibniz’s proposition have semantic content that is not contained in their letters, if by “letters” it is meant “characters of the alphabet”. This is obvious in languages with aspirated breathing marks, where the operation of emphasis possesses a symbol within the language, but English can be deceptive in this regard, for italicization or boldening are not normally considered a linguistic symbol, even though they possess no warrant to belong to any other classification.

Leibniz’s emphasis is a form of naming that would more naturally be represented with quotation marks. The lefthand side of the proposition selects the name of being, “being”, preparing it for the operation of definition. The selection is then equated through the copula of being to the righthand side, which defines the named being as the being of the name of the article through which it is selected for naming. A “being” is nothing more than an index attached to a being.

The operation of naming can be understood in terms of pure direction. A rule is given that picks a name from the domain of names and assigns to it an object in the domain of objects. In the preceding sentence, “object” is not necessarily equivalent to “thing”, and might be more precisely described as “an indeterminate being”.

Consider the infinite sequence of squares,

\[\{ 0, 1, 4, 9, 16, ... \}\]

In what sense is this sequence (set, class, abstraction) equivalent to the following function?

\[f(n) = n ^ 2\]

f” is a formal statement, devoid of content. It must be interpretted to have any meaning. This equivalence can only be maintained if the function “f” is understood to be assigning a name from the domain of natural numbers to each element in the domain of squares. “f” names each element in the sequence of squares by indexing them. In other words, “0”” is the name of first square, “1”” is the name of the second square, “4”” is the name of the third square, et cetera.

Frege was the first to recognize the mathematical function as possessing the formal structure of a “name”.

Language cannot provide content; language is only capable of resolving content into formal structures.

November#

The desire for exegesis cannot be met without recourse to personal experience, and in introducing the subjective element, the exegesis itself is undone. One wants a formal deduction, a series of arguments absolute and pure, proceeding from a starting point whose self-evidence is immanent. One wants to find the words to lay upon this thing called life like a map, to show what it is and how it is to be understood. We seek a science that explains what it is to be, that will, as part of its apparatus, integrate our very consciousness into its fabric and render unto us a divine sort of revelation.

This is the essential human delusion. Essential, because it resides in every activity; there is nothing which is that does not presuppose the law of cause and effect, and so we come to be supposing all which is must abide this fundamental law. Human, because it is our poetical curse to attach symbols to objects. Delusion, because the subject will never find itself among objects, except as an object.

We imagine the written word like a mirror, a silvered surface that reflects and reveals its point of origin through precise geometry but our thoughts are not like rays of light, and the page is no surface to preserve in perfect fashion the objects incident upon it. The word always grasps towards what it wants to represent, but fails in its approach.

Is there a series of words that explains the world’s churning? Mathematicians tells us to fix our definitions, and let logic unfold. With what definition do we start? To be, seems the most general of relations, the most primitive of terms. Thus, we initiate again an Aristotelian chain, whose history is available to any student of philsophy. Such an exercise, though worthwhile, will only yield formal results, against which we will inevitably rebel in Heideggerian fashion, and then succumb, forgetting in essence our original task.

I want to tell you what I know, but the words that I would use to give form to my thoughts escape me. I labor in vain for quiet hours. There is structure in our experience, in our lives, underneath its surface, if only it were presented, so that it might be represented in symbolic form.

It is easy to slip into solipsism, like a Cartesian fingertrap. One must remember that language presumes the presence of another. Though the world as we know it may lack facts, it never lacks form. The existence of words is testament to the communal aspect of reality, that when we are in the world, we are in the world with someone else. The world, a veil though it may be in its appearance, is substantial, because it can be described, and a decription can only exist for someone.

Let us start any exegesis with this simple proposition whose tautological nature is thus self evident:

What is said requires some one to say it.

Let us use this a ballast when the ontological investigations we undertake lead us astray, into a nihilistic miasma.

December#

The Context Problem#

As a thought experiment, suppose you encountered a string in an unknown language,

\[a = b = c\]

Without any further information about the language, nearly any interpretation can be assigned to this expression. There is a small amount of information encoded in the repetition of “=”, which imposes a light constraint on the possible interpretations, but the meaning of these interpretations is still too diverse to say with any measure of certainty what this expression could possibly mean. “=” could, for example, serve the dual role of a relativizer and an indicator, allowing such interpretations as,

lady that sings that tune

In this interpretation, “a” is assigned the meaning of “(the) lady”, “b” that of “sings” and “c” that of “tune”. Obviously, a large number, possibly infinite in size, of such expressions can be constructed.

Suppose you are provided a dictionary of primitive symbols. This dictionary fixes the meaning of the “=” to the familiar concept of equality. However, even this disambiguating assignment stills the leave door open to a myriad of interpretations. This assignment imposes only the lightest of constraints on the other word-forms in the expression. For example, it is unclear if the expression with the “equality” assignment should be interpretted as meaning,

“a = b” and “b = c”

Or

a = (b = c)

Or

(a = b) = c

In the first interpretation, “a”, “b” and “c” must represent terms within the language. In the second interpretation, “a” fills the meta-role of a truth value while “b” and “c” fill the roles of terms in the object language. In the third interpretation, “a” and “b” fill the roles of object terms while “c” fills the role of a truth value.

In other words, the assignment of the meaning of “=” imposes certain constraints on the values the other word-forms in the expression may range over, but ambiguity still remains. Indeed, it may argued a quanta of ambiguity is always present in any interpretation assigned to a string of symbols.

The essential context problem boils down to: what word-form in an expression should be treated as primitive in order to be used as a foundation upon which to build the subsequent interpretation.